Love

love.jpg

Can love be quantified?

Henri Bergson posits that the tendency to quantify things or experiences derives from social influence. This is because such quantification occurs through the measures and representations that have been installed by the institutions, perspectives, and languages, of human, collective existence. The sciences, and the social sciences, exemplify this quantifying tendency, in symbolising the world via calculable, comparable data. The integration of the sciences and the social sciences could therefore be helpful in determinations of [Person “x”]‘s possible identification of measurable units of love.

What must also be taken into consideration, though, is Bergson’s complementary concern that from this tendency are said to emerge quantifiable constructions of features of the world and our experience of it that might not really be quantifiable. This speaks to the tension between (i) what is perceived to be the socially constructed quantification of a thing/experience, versus (ii) what is presumed to be the real-natural state of a thing/experience.

In terms of love, we can review four positions which operate from within this tension. This will allow us to appraise how [Person “x”] might identify the units which comprise a love that [Person “x”] assumes is quantifiable, and the responses that [Person “x”] would face. Click on each position below to expand/contract its supporting argument:

1. Extreme social constructionist. The social construction of love misrepresents what is real-natural about love.

i. [Person “x”] engages studies of love to evidence the measurable units of love.

ii. [Science study “y”] studies the physiological changes that are experienced when love is reported to be felt…or…[Social science study “z”] studies the behaviours that a society has defined as indicating love.

iii. Does [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] identify measurable units of these physiological changes or behavioural patterns that comprise love?

If no…

iv. [Person “x”] does not identify measurable units of quantified love.

If yes…

v. [Person “x”] identifies measurable units of quantified love.

The extreme social constructionist responds…

vi. The sciences are socially constructed institutions/perspectives.

vii. Socially constructed perspectives misrepresent what is real-natural about the world.

viii. [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] is a socially constructed perspective of love.

ix. Even if measurable units of quantified love are posited by [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”], such units misrepresent what is real-natural about love.

x. The love that [Person “x”] quantifies misrepresents what is real-natural about love.

This position is that scientific experimentation, techniques, perspectives, and theories, could have been developed in myriad ways, depending on relevant social influences. Consequently, the resulting scientific results must be dependent upon how society has shaped them. This contingently social factor in the production of scientific truths is contrasted from what are posited to be the necessarily timeless truths or realities of the world. By looking at love through a contingently socially constructed lens (the sciences are interpreted to be such lenses), the extreme social constructionist’s position demands that the measurable units that might be posited scientifically regarding love, never represent love as it really, naturally is.

2. Exclusive social constructionist. The social construction of love is all that love ever is.

i. – vi. as per position 1.

The exclusive social constructionist responds…

vii. Love is also a social construction.

viii. If love is a social construction, and the sciences are social constructions, the scientific study of love measures the only reality of love.

ix. Does [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] identify measurable units of this love?

If no…

x. [Person “x”] does not identify measurable units of quantified love.

If yes…

xi. [Person “x”] identifies measurable units of quantified love.

This position is that love is a concept that societies have created. Societies define the criteria for what comprises love accordingly. These criteria, either physiological, behavioural, or both, are the signs of love. If a society conceives of love by such signs, and love is considered to be nothing but its social conceptualisation, then the measurement of these signs is duly interpreted to measure love’s reality.

This differs from the extreme social constructionist position that is presented above in one key regard; the exclusive social constructionist avoids the supposition of a separate natural reality of love that the social construction of it must explain, access, or discover. Rather, for the exclusive social constructionist, love is a concept that is believed to only ever have a social reality.

This latter point presents the greatest issue with this position. Will it be adequate for [Person “x”] (or indeed for anyone), to state that love is only a contingent, social construction, with no other reality? If [Person “x”] wishes to argue that love has a reality beyond how a society has come to conceive of it, [Person “x”] then needs to tackle the contestation in position 1 from the extreme social constructionist.

3. Real-natural social constructionist. The social construction of love is a part of what is real-natural about love.

i. – vi. as per position 1.

vii. What is socially constructed is a part of what is real-natural.

viii. If what is socially constructed is a part of what is real-natural, [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] is a part of what is real-natural.

ix. Does [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] identify measurable units of love.

If no…

x. [Person “x”] does not identify measurable units of quantified love.

If yes…

xi. [Person “x”] identifies measurable units of quantified love.

This position is that what is real-natural expresses itself in social ways. Society, which is a part of what is real-natural, declares through its languages and customs (including its scientific studies), that this feature (love) of what is real-natural is quantifiable. The social construction of love in quantifiable terms is a part of what is real-natural about love. This interpretation resolves the problem of a real-natural world that social perspectives only misrepresent, as found in the extreme social constructionist’s position.

If what is social is real-natural, and vice-versa, then not only is the social construction of love a part of what is real-natural, but also, what is real-natural about love is a social reality. If the real-natural, as society, is said to conceive of love quantifiably, and to identify love’s measurable units, then what is real-natural about love is that it is quantified via measurable units.

Not incidentally, this position intersects most coherently with what might be referred to as the “realist” position. The realist would posit that our scientific impressions of what is real-natural do accurately represent what is real-natural. This point must be qualified with the observation that the realist might baulk at the definition of scientific production merely as a contingent, socially constructed, institution. Given that Counting sheep is occupied with Bergsonian-inspired concerns regarding the tendency to socially (mis)construct all features of the world quantifiably, this realist position, in avoiding themes of social constructionism, is not included in these considerations.

4. Incorrect real-natural social constructionist. The social construction of love is a part of what is real-natural about love, but is incorrect about love.

i. – vi. as per position 1.

vii. What is socially constructed is a part of what is real-natural.

viii. If what is socially constructed is a part of what is real-natural, [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] is a part of what is real-natural.

ix. Does [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] identify measurable units of love.

If no…

x. [Person “x”] does not identify measurable units of quantified love.

If yes…

xi. [Person “x”] identifies measurable units of quantified love.

The incorrect real-natural social constructionist responds…

v. [Science study “y”] or [Social science study “z”] is a part of what is real-natural and is incorrect that love is quantifiable.

vi. [Person “x”] does not identify measurable units of quantified love.

Alternatively, the interpretation might be that what is real-natural, socially posits that love is quantifiable when actually it is not. The curiosity in this position is that what is real-natural is presenting as a social form of the real-natural, which in perceiving a feature (love) of what is real-natural, is incorrect about that feature (love) of what is real-natural.

What is forwarded in this position is not that incorrect socially constructed quantifications of love represent a mutual exclusion between (i) the social, scientific, perspective/construction of love, and (ii) what is real-natural about love. Instead, as per position 3, both the social construction of love, and what is real-natural about love, are simultaneously social and real-natural. Whilst units of measurement do not exist for this feature (love) of what is real-natural, what is socially constructed is not said to be excluded from what is real-natural when conceiving of love incorrectly (quantifiably).

Rather, what is being forwarded in this position is that what is real-natural comprises all possible social perspectives/constructions of this feature (love) of what is real-natural. Every social perspective/construction, according to this position, comes from nowhere but from what is real-natural, after all. One of these perspectives/constructions is that which posits that love is quantifiable, even when there are actually no measurable units comprising such quantification, and therefore no quantification of love whatsoever.

A reason that such units of measurement do not exist, and that the quantification of love is incorrect, could relate to the way in which love manifests. [Person “x”] perceives a difference in the degree or size of the love that manifests. However, for this position it could be stated that love emerges environmentally, structurally, and circumstantially. With each set of different circumstances comes a different kind, rather than a different magnitude, of love.

If the kind of love that manifests is contingent upon the environment in which it manifests, there can be no standardised units across differently manifested loves. This problematises the possible quantification of, and comparison between, an individual’s manifestations of love over time. Similarly it contests the possibility of comparing the love between different individuals. Each instantiation of love is instead qualitatively incomparable, if it is deemed to manifest circumstantially.